Abstract
Based on considerations of justice, healthcare workers must be able to rely on support and protection from the societies in which they work. Prioritisation of healthcare workers for vaccines may be a way to maintain a functioning healthcare system.
During the coronavirus disease 2019 (COVID-19) pandemic, some healthcare facilities have, at times, reached the limits of their capacity to handle the surge in patient volume. Hospital beds and other medical resources became scarce as a consequence. Healthcare workers (HCWs) – both clinical and non-clinical – were required to increase their workload, under extremely stressful circumstances.
HCWs are routinely exposed to numerous stressors, which results in high rates of burnout, post-traumatic stress disorder, and suicide, especially among those working in high intensity environments [1]. This has been especially true during the COVID-19 pandemic [2]. Physically stressful working conditions and witnessing the suffering and death of large numbers of patients take a toll. Further, when resources cannot fully meet demand, HCWs may experience moral distress due to rationing decisions [3]. In addition, being confronted with a highly contagious pathogen like the severe acute respiratory syndrome coronavirus 2 (SARS-CoV-2), there is also the fear of becoming infected oneself or spreading the infection to one's family (see table 1) [4]. This stress may contribute to physical exhaustion and feelings of fear and anxiety, sleep-disorders and insomnia, or even burnout and depression [2]. All of this is compounded in a situation like a pandemic where the effects are felt beyond the work environment, giving HCWs the sense that there is no way to escape the pressures outside the hospital. Anxiety is further heightened by the uncertainty about when the pandemic will end or how bad it will get. With all of this psychological trauma, some HCWs will need extra time away from the hospital, some may never return to their jobs. As a consequence, healthcare facilities and systems could lose HCWs precisely at a time when they are needed most, further aggravating the situation of scarcity created by the increased demand. Therefore, it is crucial to keep working conditions as safe as possible in times of crisis. As patient surge reaches critical limits, tasks not absolutely necessary for patient care should be reduced as much as possible, while preserving safety.
Stressors for healthcare workers (HCWs) during the coronavirus disease 2019 (COVID-19) pandemic
Ongoing support for HCWs is critical at all levels, for instance, from family, friends, and colleagues, as well as healthcare institutions, professional organisations, government and society at large. The support must be aimed at protecting and maintaining the mental and physical wellbeing of HCWs and early identification when they are at risk. For the individual, this support may come in many forms, such as meditation, exercise, creative arts therapy, and religious or spiritual activities. Furthermore, interprofessional teams caring for patients, especially in intensive care units, need to be assisted in fostering community [5]. Psychological support for those in need may include a trauma psychologist in those regions deeply affected by the pandemic. This support could also help counteract “social contagion”, an aggravation of symptoms among peers [6].
The issue of supporting HCWs, however, is not only a question of physical and mental health; there are moral questions of responsibility, solidarity and justice at stake. HCWs not only have a professional and legal obligation to provide care for patients, but also a moral obligation [7]. This moral obligation is reflected by the acceptance of professional codes like the Hippocratic oath and codes of various medical and allied health associations. However, the extent to which this obligation is appropriate in a situation where the acceptance of it would entail a significant threat to the HCWs own health and well-being is debatable. Neither heroism, nor self-sacrifice can be demanded based on a perceived moral obligation [7].
Moral imperatives – and, similarly, the legal and professional obligations derived from them – cannot be a unilateral commitment by HCWs; they should instead be considered as part of a societal contract consisting of mutual interests, rights and duties. HCWs should be able to rely on reciprocal obligations from others [8]. The scope of these reciprocal obligations is similarly context- and situation-dependent. In the setting of the COVID-19 pandemic, HCWs must be able to rely on a wide array of support, as well as responsible behavior by other members of society (table 2). For instance, situations in which HCWs put themselves at risk due to the lack of personal protective equipment (PPE) must be strenuously avoided [9]. Similarly, reciprocal responsibility and solidarity also includes responsible behavior of all members of society. Contact restrictions, social distancing, and the wearing of face masks in public can help save HCWs, health facilities and health systems from being overburdened. Finally, compensation for surviving dependents of HCWs who became infected during their work and died should be part of these reciprocal obligations as a matter of solidarity.
Reciprocal obligations for members society with the goal of limiting the number of infected patients and reducing strain on the healthcare system
When demand for resources overwhelms supply, the inability to provide standard of care due to lack of staffing or equipment, raises not only moral but also legal questions [10]. HCWs, and in particular physicians, may be at risk for being sued for not providing a normal standard of care despite being in a crisis for which they themselves could not reasonably be held responsible [11]. Working under a crisis standard of care that may, of necessity, be well below the ordinary standard of care, can be a source of extreme stress for all HCWs. This stress should not be compounded by the fear of legal prosecution, whether civil or criminal. The reciprocal responsibility of society at large should therefore entail the protection of HCWs in general from legal action based on a failure to provide an impossible-to-achieve standard of care in times when clinicians are forced to practice under crisis standards of care.
One additional remedy that has been proposed is to prioritise such individuals for vaccines and treatments that are limited in availability, with the rationale resting on the instrumental value of HCWs as well as on reciprocity or even reward for their commitment to society [12]. This argument has merit, particularly in the context of preserving the HCW workforce, when it comes to the distribution of a vaccine that won't be equally available for all from the outset. However, it will be challenging to balance this argument against prioritisation according to medical need. Preserving the lives of HCWs may help preserve one of the scarcest resources in this pandemic and thereby potentially save more lives through their work at the bedside. However, prioritisation of HCWs will disproportionately benefit the educated and thereby aggravate existing social and racial disparities, which may be in conflict with egalitarian principles and equity. Several prioritisation guidelines for the distribution of COVID-19 vaccines acknowleged prioritisation of frontline HCWs. However, other guidelines avoid taking a position with regard to favoring HCWs over elderly patients by awarding both groups the vaccine with equal priority [13, 14]. Both approaches have merit, but considering all arguments we advocate for prioritisation of frontline HCWs for SARS-CoV-2 vaccines.
Considering a broader range of treatments beyond vaccines, we believe prioritisation of HCWs for receipt of scarce resources should be subordinate to other more convincing principles. It is impossible to fairly judge instrumental value from the socially useful behavior of a person, and weigh it against other values. In addition, the judgement of instrumental value brings with it considerable danger of discrimination through overrating of an alleged instrumental value compared to morally competing principles, such as non-discrimination based on race, gender, age, disability, or socioeconomic status.
The COVID-19 pandemic has put many health facilities and systems and even entire societies under unprecedented levels of stress. For reasons of justice and in order not to jeopardise the functioning of the health sector, HCWs must be able to rely on broad support to fulfill their duties for the benefit of society. Protecting and preserving the healthcare workforce has a direct bearing on the functioning of the entire healthcare system, which is paramount for the well-being of all societies.
Acknowledgements
Not applicable.
Footnotes
Support statement: No funding was provided specific to this work.
Author contributions: AS wrote the first draft of the manuscript following discussions with DB and JRC. All co-authors revised the manuscript and added key content. All co-authors read and approved the final manuscript.
Conflict of interest: Dr. Supady reports grants and personal fees from CytoSorbents , personal fees from Abiomed, outside the submitted work;.
Conflict of interest: Dr. Curtis reports grants from National Institutes of Health, grants and personal fees from Cambia Health Foundation, grants from National Palliative Care Research Center, outside the submitted work;.
Conflict of interest: Dr. Brown has nothing to disclose.
Conflict of interest: Dr. Duerschmied has nothing to disclose.
Conflict of interest: Mrs von Zepelin has nothing to disclose.
Conflict of interest: Dr. Moss has nothing to disclose.
Conflict of interest: Dr. Brodie reports grants from ALung Technologies, personal fees from Baxter, personal fees from Xenios, personal fees from Abiomed, other from Hemovent, outside the submitted work;.
- Received January 14, 2021.
- Accepted January 21, 2021.
- ©The authors 2021.
This version is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Non-Commercial Licence 4.0. For commercial reproduction rights and permissions contact permissions{at}ersnet.org